• Ei tuloksia

View of Gregory Currie: Imagining and Knowing: The Shape of Fiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2020

N/A
N/A
Info
Lataa
Protected

Academic year: 2022

Jaa "View of Gregory Currie: Imagining and Knowing: The Shape of Fiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2020"

Copied!
3
0
0

Kokoteksti

(1)

MedieKultur | Journal of media and communication research | ISSN 1901-9726 Book Review

Published by SMID | Society of Media researchers In Denmark | www.smid.dk Th e online version of this text can be found open access at https://tidsskrift.dk/mediekultur

147

When you last read a literary novel or watched a challenging fi ction fi lm—say, Tolstoy’s Anna Karenina or Welles’ Citizen Kane—did you learn anything substantive about the real world? Did you come to know or understand important things of which you were previously ignorant? Many people would answer such questions affi rmatively and as suredly: “Of course I did! How could I not learn something important about human aff airs by engaging with these monumental works of human creativity?” If pressed to say what exactly it is that they learned, however, their answer would likely be neither assured nor very exact. Th ey might claim to have gained insight into something called “the human condition.” Or perhaps they will suggest that they now know, in some richer and fuller sense, how power corrupts.

Gregory Currie, a professor of philosophy at the University of York, thinks not. In Imagining and Knowing: Th e Shape of Fiction, he takes critical aim at the many ambitious claims that have been made for fi ction’s educative potential—its capacity to reveal deep human truths, build skills, and refi ne sensibilities. He starts by noting an evidential double standard:

Th ose who condemn various kinds of fi ction as leading to ignorance, error, or bad behav- iour are rightly challenged to provide evidence for their claims, and the few philosophers who have taken up the cause have generally been careful to seek evidential support for

MedieKultur 2020, 68, 147-149

Gregory Currie:

Imagining and Knowing: Th e Shape of Fiction.

Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2020

Jens Kjeldgaard-Christiansen

(2)

MedieKultur 68

148 Jens Kjeldgaard-Christiansen

Review: Imagining and Knowing: Th e Shape of Fiction

their case. By contrast, we fi nd books extolling the improving powers of fi ction which fail to provide, or even consider providing, any evidence. (p. 5)

Most of the book is devoted to critical discussion of what would count as good evidence that we learn valuable lessons from media fi ctions, and to showing that, in many cases, there are philosophical and psychological reasons to be skeptical that we do. “One reason for a cautious attitude to the idea that we learn from fi ction,” as Currie rightly notes, “is that we want it to be true” (p. 4). Other reasons range from the analytic and concep- tual to the grittily empirical. Currie argues, for example, that our fi ctional engagements are often marked by low epistemic vigilance. We are typically not motivated to inquire into whether this or that depicted experience is actually anything like the real deal.

Compounding the issue, fi ction’s institutional structures—its departments, its publi- shing practices, its awards—are generally not very concerned with the truthfulness and verisimili tude of narrative depictions. Or at least they are nowhere near as concerned with truth as are the institutions of science. On the empirical side of things, Currie shows, among other things, that the oft-touted causal link between narrative experience and empathy is actually weak and tenuous.

Th ese arguments notwithstanding, many people are genuinely convinced that they learn important lessons from fi ction. Are they fooling themselves? Currie’s surprising answer is that they may well be, literally! His argument—the book’s weakest—starts with the philosophically respectable idea that fi ctional engagements involve

a pretence that is carried on in imagination rather than acted out in behaviour […] What I suggest now is that fi ction engages us in a further act of pretending: the pretence that we are learning from the story, not just about its characters and their doings, but, in some indirect way, about things which lie beyond the events and characters of its story, which are suggested by them and which may be intended to be communicated by means of the story. (p. 107)

I fi nd this suggestion puzzling. To what presumed fact about human psychology would the claim correspond? As Currie realizes, friends of learning from fi ction certainly do not believe that their own learning is merely pretended. What fact about them makes them pretend, then? As far as I was able to tell, Currie does not identify such a fact. He does, however, provide two considerations in favor of his suggestion. Th e fi rst is that when we pretend that fi ctional characters exist and interact, “we are naturally led to include within the scope of the pretense a wider range of pretended learning that takes in the sorts of things we often claim that fi ction really can teach us” (p. 108). In other words, the pre- tended learning may just come along for the ride. But the fact that something is learned within the scope of some pretense does not show that the learning is itself pretended.

Currie’s second point is that “as theories of what we might call broadly artistic engage- ment go, this is not an eccentric suggestion” (pp. 108-109). Maybe so, but that does not

(3)

MedieKultur 68

149 Jens Kjeldgaard-Christiansen

Review: Imagining and Knowing: Th e Shape of Fiction

make the suggestion true. In the end, I doubt there is much substance to the idea that learning from fi ction is a form of pretense.

Some critics might fault the book for a lack of focus. Part I looks closely at the connec- tion between fi ction and the imagination, whereas parts II and III deal with the connec- tion between fi ction and knowledge. Th ose are very diff erent sorts of connection, in that the former is entirely internal to the fi ctional engagement whereas the latter is not. How- ever, the arguments made in the two latter parts lean on the conceptual groundwork set out in the fi rst part, where Currie convincingly refutes recent attempts to discount or defl ate the role of the imagination in our fi ctional engagements. It is precisely because fi ction relies on the imagination, and because there is no simple route from imagining to knowing, that learning from fi ction proves such a vexing question.

Still, in this reviewer’s judgment, the affi nity between fi ction and the imagination may also provide some grounds for optimism. For perhaps it is exactly by expanding our imaginative capacities that fi ctions earn their esteem. How fi ctions might do this remains understudied, both philosophically and psychologically. We need to know much more about how diff erent media may guide or “scaff old” the human imagination—not just how they work, but how they work on us. Such imaginings as are licensed by fi lm are mainly and richly cognitive; they are about perceiving and understanding what happens on the screen. By contrast, video games may also accommodate the user’s conative states to generate self-involving, desire-driven imaginings. Film and video games thus scaff old the human imagination in very diff erent ways. If indeed fi ctions teach us anything useful and important, those teachings should have something to do with the disparate kinds of imagining licensed by their implementing media. And if indeed any such teachings go through the imagination, then it might be worth focusing, fi rst, on fi ction’s eff ects on the imagination, before then deciding where and when we should expect to fi nd any behav- ioral evidence.

Imagining and Knowing represents a strong challenge to weakly supported claims for the educative powers of fi ction. While the book focuses on literature and fi lm, it is a worthwhile read for any media scholar with a general interest in its subject.

Jens Kjeldgaard-Christiansen PhD student Department of English Aarhus University jkc@cc.au.dk

Viittaukset

LIITTYVÄT TIEDOSTOT

social imaginaries of the Information Society are influenced by complexity theory. While this claim is certainly interesting, it remains precisely a claim, as the book does not

Th e Oxford Handbook of Internet Studies, originating from the renowned Oxford Internet Institute at the University of Oxford and edited by the previous director (2002-11) Wil-

Especially in conjunction with other current works on social media logics and datafication (van Dijck & Poell, 2013), the work of Jose van Dijck constitutes a prolific

With his new and latest Communication Power (2009), he focuses his attention on communication as power and guides us on a tour de force through landscapes of international

Selfhood and the Soul: Essays On Ancient Thought and Literature in Honour of Christopher Gill (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017); Richard Sorabji, Self: Ancient and Modern

In Geoffrey Sampson, David Gil, and Peter Trudgill (eds.), Language complexity as an evolving variable. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Word order in zero-marking

Discourse and the Construction of Society, Comparative Studies of Myth, Ritual and Classification, Oxford University Press, New York and Oxford,1989 Theorizing Myth,

This paper explores “how ethnographic collaboration configures its data” via examination of three relations: between ethnography as method and writing, between leaky empirical